Feeds:
Posts
Comments

Posts Tagged ‘Ethics’

From @Harvardmed Center for Bioethics: The Medical Ethics of the Corona Virus Crisis

Reporter: Stephen J. Williams, Ph.D.

From Harvard Medical School Center for Bioethics

source: https://bioethics.hms.harvard.edu/news/medical-ethics-corona-virus-crisis

The Medical Ethics of the Corona Virus Crisis

Executive Director Christine Mitchell discusses the importance of institutions talking through the implications of their decisions with the New Yorker.

Center Executive Director Christine Mitchell spoke with the New Yorker’s Isaac Chotiner about the decisions that may need to be made on limiting movement and, potentially, rationing supplies and hospital space.

“So, in the debate about allocating resources in a pandemic, we have to work with our colleagues around what kind of space is going to be made available—which means that other people and other services have to be dislocated—what kind of supplies we’re going to have, whether we’re going to reuse them, how we will reallocate staff, whether we can have staff who are not specialists take care of patients because we have way more patients than the number of specialized staff,” says Mitchell.

Read the full Q&A in the New Yorker.

 

Note: The following is taken from the Interview in the New Yorker.

As the novel coronaviruscovid-19, spreads across the globe, governments have been taking increasingly severe measures to limit the virus’s infection rate. China, where it originated, has instituted quarantines in areas with a large number of cases, and Italy—which is now facing perhaps the most serious threat outside of China—is entirely under quarantine. In the United States, the National Guard has been deployed to manage a “containment area” in New Rochelle, New York, where one of the country’s largest clusters has emerged. As the number of cases rises, we will soon face decisions on limiting movement and, potentially, rationing supplies and hospital space. These issues will be decided at the highest level by politicians, but they are often influenced by medical ethicists, who advise governments and other institutions about the way to handle medical emergencies.

One of those ethicists, with whom I recently spoke by phone, is Christine Mitchell, the executive director at the Center for Bioethics at Harvard Medical School. Mitchell, who has master’s degrees in nursing and philosophical and religious ethics, has been a clinical ethicist for thirty years. She founded the ethics program at Boston Children’s Hospital, and has served on national and international medical-ethics commissions. During our conversation, which has been edited for length and clarity, we discussed what ethicists tend to focus on during a health crisis, how existing health-care access affects crisis response, and the importance of institutions talking through the ethical implications of their decisions.

What coronavirus-related issue has most occupied your mental space over the past weeks?

One of the things I think about but that we don’t often have an opportunity to talk about, when we are mostly focussing on what clinicians are doing and trying to prepare for, is the more general ways this affects our society. People get sick out there in the real world, and then they come to our hospitals, but, when they are sick, a whole bunch of them don’t have health insurance, or are afraid to come to a hospital, or they don’t have coverage for sick time or taking a day off when their child is sick, so they send their child to school. So these all have very significant influences on our ability to manage population health and community transmission that aren’t things that nurses and physicians and people who work in acute-care hospitals and clinics can really affect. They are elements of the way our society is structured and has failed to meet the needs of our general population, and they influence our ability to manage a crisis like this.

Is there anything specifically about a pandemic or something like coronavirus that makes these issues especially acute?

If a person doesn’t have health insurance and doesn’t come to be tested or treated, and if they don’t have sick-time coverage and can’t leave work, so they teach at a school, or they work at a restaurant, or do events that have large numbers of people, these are all ways in which the spread of a virus like this has to be managed—and yet can’t be managed effectively because of our social-welfare policies, not just our health-care resources.

Just to take a step back, and I want to get back to coronavirus stuff, but what got you interested in medical ethics?

What got me interested were the actual kinds of problems that came up when I was taking care of patients, starting as early as when I was in nursing school and was taking care of a patient who, as a teen-ager, had a terminal kind of cancer that his parents didn’t want him to know about, and which the health-care team had decided to defer to the parents. And yet I was spending every day taking care of him, and he was really puzzled about why he was so sick and whether he was going to get better, and so forth. And so of course I was faced with this question of, What do I do if he asks me? Which, of course, he did.

And this question about what you should tell an adolescent and whether the deference should be to his parents’ judgment about what’s best for him, which we would ordinarily respect, and the moral demands of the relationship that you have with a patient, was one of the cases that reminded me that there’s a lot more to being a nurse or a health-care provider than just knowing how to give cancer chemotherapy and change a bed, or change a dressing, or whatever. That a lot of it is in the relationship you have with a patient and the kinds of ethical choices they and their families are facing. They need your information, but also your help as they think things through. That’s the kind of thing that got me interested in it. There are a whole host of those kinds of cases, but they’re more individual cases.

As I began to work in a hospital as an ethicist, I began to worry about the broader organizational issues, like emergency preparedness. Some years ago, here in Boston, I had a joint appointment running the ethics program at Children’s Hospital and doing clinical ethics at Harvard Medical School. We pulled together a group, with the Department of Public Health and the emergency-preparedness clinicians in the Harvard-affiliated hospitals, to look at what the response within the state of Massachusetts should be to big, major disasters or rolling pandemics, and worked on some guidelines together.

When you looked at the response of our government, in a place like Washington State or in New York City, what things, from a medical-ethics perspective, are you noticing that are either good or maybe not so good?

To be candid and, probably, to use language that’s too sharp for publication, I’m appalled. We didn’t get ourselves ready. We’ve had outbreaks—sars in 2003, H1N1 in 2009, Ebola in 2013, Zika in 2016. We’ve known, and the general population in some ways has known. They even have movies like “Contagion” that did a great job of sharing publicly what this is like, although it is fictional, and that we were going to have these kinds of infectious diseases in a global community that we have to be prepared to handle. And we didn’t get ourselves as ready, in most cases, as we should have. There have been all these cuts to the C.D.C. budget, and the person who was the Ebola czar no longer exists in the new Administration.

And it’s not just this Administration. But the thing about this Administration that perhaps worries me the most is a fundamental lack of respect for science and the facts. Managing the crisis from a public-relations perspective and an economic, Dow Jones perspective are important, but they shouldn’t be fudging the facts. And that’s the piece that makes me feel most concerned—and not just as an ethicist. And then, of course, I want to see public education and information that’s forthright and helps people get the treatment that they need. But the disrespect for the public, and not providing honest information, is . . . yeah, that’s pretty disconcerting.

SOURCE

https://www.newyorker.com/news/q-and-a/the-medical-ethics-of-the-coronavirus-crisis

See more on this and #COVID19 on this Online Open Access Journal at our Coronavirus Portal at

https://pharmaceuticalintelligence.com/coronavirus-portal/

Read Full Post »

unchecked spread of engineered genes

Larry H. Bernstein, MD, FCAP, Curator

LPBI

Reining in Gene Drives

Researchers have developed two methods to avoid the unchecked spread of engineered genes through wild populations.

By Karen Zusi | Nov 18, 2015    http://www.the-scientist.com//?articles.view/articleNo/44501/title/Reining-in-Gene-Drives/

2.1.4.6

2.1.4.6   Unchecked Spread of Engineered Genes, Volume 2 (Volume Two: Latest in Genomics Methodologies for Therapeutics: Gene Editing, NGS and BioInformatics, Simulations and the Genome Ontology), Part 2: CRISPR for Gene Editing and DNA Repair

“Gene drive” is a phenomenon that causes a gene to be inherited at a rate faster than Mendelian principles would dictate. It relies on genes that can copy themselves onto a corresponding location in a paired chromosome, thereby overriding typical allele inheritance patterns. In conjunction with CRISPR/Cas9, gene drives can be created with almost any DNA sequence, raising questions about the risk of engineered genes spreading quickly through a population. But a team of researchers from Harvard University published a study this week (November 16) in Nature Biology that offers some safety constraints on the system.

description of the first CRISPR/Cas9 gene drive system was published in March by a team at the University of California, San Diego, and showed rapid spreading of a normally recessive phenotype inDrosophila. Other labs are researching the system’s potential to wipe out insect-borne diseases such as malaria by spreading mutated genes throughout a mosquito population. But the strategy carries the risk of accidental contamination of wild populations.

“We have a responsibility to keep our experiments confined to the laboratory,” Kevin Esvelt, an evolutionary engineer and coauthor on the paper, told Nature. “The basic lesson is: if you don’t have to build a gene drive that can spread through a wild population, then don’t.”

Esvelt’s team developed safety protocols—ways to prevent or reverse a released gene drive—using the yeast Saccharomyces cerevisia. One technique genetically separates the components necessary to create a gene drive, putting one half directly in the yeast genome and the other half on an external strand of DNA. The researchers also developed a method that uses one gene drive to overwrite the effects of another.

While these techniques are intended to stem the potential for gene drives in light of safety concerns, Esvelt told Nature that he hopes the scientific community will thoughtfully evaluate gene drives rather than dismiss them. “Should we use gene drive to eliminate malaria? Should we use it to replace broadly toxic insecticides? These questions all have to be considered separately,” he told Nature. “This paper is really about making sure we don’t blow it in the meantime and obviate the chance to talk about all of this.”

Safeguarding CRISPR-Cas9 gene drives in yeast

James E DiCarloAlejandro ChavezSven L DietzKevin M Esvelt & George M Church

Nature Biotechnology(2015)       http://dx.doi.org:/10.1038/nbt.3412

RNA-guided gene drives capable of spreading genomic alterations made in laboratory organisms through wild populations could be used to address environmental and public health problems. However, the possibility of unintended genome editing occurring through the escape of strains from laboratories, coupled with the prospect of unanticipated ecological change, demands caution. We report the efficacy of CRISPR-Cas9 gene drive systems in wild and laboratory strains of the yeastSaccharomyces cerevisiae. Furthermore, we address concerns surrounding accidental genome editing by developing and validating methods of molecular confinement that minimize the risk of unwanted genome editing. We also present a drive system capable of overwriting the changes introduced by an earlier gene drive. These molecular safeguards should enable the development of safe CRISPR gene drives for diverse organisms.

Figure 1: Mechanism and population-level effect of endonuclease gene drives.close

Mechanism and population-level effect of endonuclease gene drives.

(a) Homing endonucleases cut competing alleles, inducing the cell to repair the damage by copying the endonuclease gene. (b) By converting heterozygous germline cells into homozygotes containing two copies (teal), gene drives increase

Figure 3: Gene drives and cargo genes remain intact upon copying and can spread by targeting both nonessential and essential genes.close

Gene drives and cargo genes remain intact upon copying and can spread by targeting both nonessential and essential genes.

(a) The ADE2-targeting gene drive was modified to carry URA3 as a cargo gene. (b) Diploids produced by mating wild-typeURA3 haploid yeast with haploids encoding the gene drive carrying URA3 were allowed to sporulate and tetrads dissec…

CRISPR Chain Reaction

A powerful new CRISPR/Cas9 tool can be used to produce homozygous mutations within a generation, but scientists call for caution.

By Jenny Rood | March 19, 2015     http://www.the-scientist.com/?articles.view/articleNo/42504/title/CRISPR-Chain-Reaction/

A new genetic-editing technique based on integratingCRISPR/Cas9 technology into a Drosophila melanogaster genome can make homozygous mutants in half the time it would take using traditional crosses, according to a paper published today (March 19) in Science.

“The study is well done and also very elegant,” said Ji-Long Liu of the University of Oxford who was not involved in the research, but helped to develop CRISPR/Cas9 in Drosophila. Liu called the method “a really clever way to . . . make the magic happen.”

A rare mosaic female fly, with a lighter left half mutated by MCR and a wild-type darker right half.
UCSD, VALENTINO GANTZ AND ETHAN BIER

Safety upgrade found for gene-editing technique

Tweak reduces chance of a mutation escaping into the wild, and can help to undo a mutation after it has spread.

Heidi Ledford          http://www.nature.com/news/safety-upgrade-found-for-gene-editing-technique-1.18799

http://www.nature.com/polopoly_fs/7.31406.1447687781!/image/1.18799.jpg_gen/derivatives/landscape_630/1.18799.jpg

A method that can spread genetic changes rapidly through populations could aid the fight against the malaria parasite, shown here infecting red blood cells.

A genome-editing method that could allow researchers to rapidly engineer entire populations has had an important upgrade. A US team has added safeguards to reduce the chances that such ‘gene drives’ will escape the laboratory, and found a way to erase the genetic mutations after they have spread.

Gene drives hold the potential to wipe out insect-borne diseases and can speed up some genetic studies in the laboratory. But if released into the wild — whether intentionally or not — gene drives could irrevocably scar entire ecosystems.

The safeguards, published today in Nature Biotechnology1, may calm some fears about the technology. One of the techniques provides a way of genetically separating the components that fuel a gene drive, so that the engineered mutation will not spread as rapidly through a population. Another is a molecular ‘undo’ button: sending a second gene drive out to undo the effects of the first.

“We have a responsibility to keep our experiments confined to the laboratory,” says Kevin Esvelt, an evolutionary engineer at the Wyss Institute for Biologically Inspired Engineering at Harvard University in Boston, Massachusetts, and an author of the paper. “The basic lesson is: if you don’t have to build a gene drive that can spread through a wild population, then don’t.”

New life

The concept of a gene drive is an old one that was given new life by the advent of a genome-editing technique called CRISPR–Cas9. It allows researchers to make targeted changes to a genome with unprecedented ease and versatility.

Esvelt and others quickly realized that this technique could be used to engineer a gene drive by incorporating the genes encoding the Cas9 enzyme, which cuts DNA, and the guide RNAs, which direct Cas9 to a specific site, into the genome. Once present on one chromosome, the system can copy itself and the desired genome modification to the other chromosome, thus racing more rapidly through a population than a mutation would normally spread.

The first demonstration of this was published in March2 by developmental biologists Valentino Gantz and Ethan Bier at the University of California, San Diego. The team used gene drives to speed up genetic studies in certain species of fruit flies. But the publication kicked off concerns that the gene drive might escape from the lab into the wild, and the US National Academies of Sciences, Engineering and Medicine tasked a committee with evaluating the benefits and risks of the technology.

Even so, some researchers have embraced the approach, particularly as a means to prevent the transmission of insect-borne diseases such as malaria, says Esvelt. George Church, a bioengineer also at the Wyss Institute and a co-author on the latest report, predicts that gene drives to wipe out malaria and the tick-borne Lyme disease will be developed within the next two years. Esvelt is also collaborating with tropical-disease specialist Paul Brindley of George Washington University in Washington DC to study the application of gene drive to wiping out schistosomiasis, a disease caused by parasitic trematode worms.

Safety measures

But Esvelt worries that an accident could undermine the technique before it has a chance to prove its worth. “If anyone messes up and a gene drive gets out into the wild, there will be a huge media circus,” he says. “The message will be that scientists cannot be trusted to deal with this technology, and we will be set back by years.”

So he and his colleagues decided to develop safety measures using the yeast Saccharomyces cerevisiae. The organism is easy to work with in the laboratory and unlikely to spread a gene drive into wild populations because of its infrequent sexual reproduction.

Read Full Post »

Reporter: Aviva Lev-Ari, PhD, RN

 

HEALTH LAW, ETHICS, AND HUMAN RIGHTS

Ethical Considerations in Studying Drug Safety — The Institute of Medicine Report

Michelle M. Mello, J.D., Ph.D., Steven N. Goodman, M.D., M.H.S., Ph.D., and Ruth R. Faden, Ph.D., M.P.H.

August 22, 2012 (10.1056/NEJMhle1207160)

The tumult arising from revelations of serious safety risks associated with widely prescribed drugs, including rosiglitazone (Avandia, GlaxoSmithKline), rofecoxib (Vioxx, Merck), and celecoxib (Celebrex, Pfizer), has led to widespread recognition that improvement is needed in our national system of ensuring drug safety. Notwithstanding federal legislation in 2007 that strengthened the authority of the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) in the postmarketing period,1 critical weaknesses in the national system persist.

Central to these weaknesses are dilemmas surrounding not only the science but also the ethics of drug-safety research,2 many of which came to the fore in the heated public debate about the Thiazolidinedione Intervention with Vitamin D Evaluation (TIDE) trial, which compared the cardiovascular outcomes of long-term treatment with rosiglitazone with those of pioglitazone (Actos, Takeda) in patients with type 2 diabetes.3 At the request of the FDA, an Institute of Medicine (IOM) committee, on which we served, was convened to examine the ethics and science of FDA-required postmarketing safety research. In this article, we review the key ethics findings from the committee’s May 1, 2012, report4 and offer some reflections on the challenges ahead.

LESSONS FROM THE TIDE TRIAL

In May 2008, the FDA ordered the manufacturer of rosiglitazone, GlaxoSmithKline, to conduct a trial in response to evidence from meta-analyses that rosiglitazone was associated with a higher risk of myocardial infarction and death from cardiovascular causes than placebo or medications that were not based on nonthiazolidinedione comparators.5,6 Other studies suggested that pioglitazone, an alternative thiazolidinedione, was not associated with such risks.7,8 Before enrollment began, some argued that the evidence of the inferior safety of rosiglitazone was strong enough to make the trial ethically unjustifiable. Two FDA epidemiologists wrote in a 2008 memorandum that a head-to-head trial “would be unethical and exploitative” and that even a robust informed-consent process could not overcome the problem.9 This was not the consensus FDA view, which was that the uncertainty regarding the cardiovascular risks associated with rosiglitazone, as well as those associated with pioglitazone, was sufficient to justify a trial.10

These concerns triggered a February 2010 letter from members of Congress to the FDA demanding a justification for the trial and alleging that the consent form did not provide adequate risk information.11 In response, FDA Commissioner Margaret Hamburg expanded the FDA investigation of the safety of rosiglitazone, obtained advice from an FDA advisory committee, and asked the IOM to convene our committee.6 Although the FDA advisory committee recommended that the TIDE trial be continued if rosiglitazone was permitted to remain on the market, in September 2010, the FDA halted the trial and placed stringent new restrictions on the availability of rosiglitazone.12,13

The TIDE experience made the FDA appreciate the need for greater attention to the ethics of postmarketing research. First, it posed questions about what standard of evidence about drug risk justifies a decision by the FDA to require postmarketing research, particularly randomized trials, as well as what evidence could render such trials unacceptable. Second, it raised questions about what ethical obligations the FDA has to patients who participate in these studies. Finally, it highlighted a potential FDA role in ensuring that institutional review boards (IRBs) are completely informed in their efforts to protect study participants. Although major deficiencies with the TIDE consent form were identified by some FDA scientists and, later, by the IOM committee (Table 1TABLE 1Major Deficiencies in the Informed-Consent Form for the TIDE Trial.),4,9 the TIDE investigators countered that it had been approved by “480 ethics committees and IRBs.”14 However, the language of the consent form, the trial design, and the materials supporting the justification of the trial raised a question for the IOM committee about whether these bodies adequately understood the nature of the evidence that gave rise to the trial. The IOM committee proposed a framework for evaluating the ethics of FDA-required postmarketing research15 and made a number of ethics findings and recommendations.4

Ethical Responsibilities of the FDA

The IOM committee began by noting that the public health mission of the FDA gives rise to potentially competing ethical obligations “to protect the public’s health by having strong science on which to base regulatory decisions” and “to protect participants in research that it requires.”4Requiring a postmarketing study is an ethical decision, reflecting a weighing of these values.

The committee described the conditions that must be present to justify a decision to require a postmarketing study. The FDA should require postmarketing research only when, first, the uncertainty about the benefit–risk balance of a drug is so great that a responsible decision about its regulatory status cannot be made on the basis of existing evidence; second, the research will reduce this uncertainty; third, the FDA will use the research results expeditiously to make a regulatory decision; and fourth, sufficient protections for research participants can be ensured.

The committee argued that when the FDA requires a postmarketing study, it assumes a measure of ethical responsibility for the welfare of the study participants; exercise of that responsibility cannot be handed off to contractors or the industry sponsor. The responsibility is particularly strong when the patients’ treatment is determined by the study, such as in a randomized trial, linking any adverse outcomes directly to a regulatory decision to require a study of that type. This determination led to one of the most important recommendations from the IOM committee: the responsibilities of the FDA to research participants mean that it should mandate a randomized design only if the FDA “has concluded that an observational study could not provide the necessary information [to help answer the important public health question at issue], that an RCT [randomized, controlled trial] is likely to generate the information within the necessary timeframe, and that the necessary RCT is ethically acceptable.” This recommendation comports with but adds some further conditions to the current legal authority of the FDA under the FDA Amendments Act of 2007, which empowers the agency to require a randomized trial if it cannot obtain the data it needs from an observational study.1

In light of the critiques of the TIDE trial as inherently unethical, the committee addressed the justifiability of trials in which participants may encounter a net increase in risk, as compared with ordinary clinical care, but no realistic prospect of personal benefit. It argued that such trials can be justified only if they are necessary to answer a critically important public health question, if the potential risk is acceptable and minimized, and if special safeguards are in place, including a highly explicit informed-consent process to ensure that patients understand that they are potentially shouldering additional risk solely to contribute to the public good.

Specific actions that the FDA should take to meet its ethical obligations include specifying the study design, title, end points, and primary analyses; identifying design features that it views as ethically and scientifically indispensable; and, for clinical trials, specifying a safety-monitoring scheme. The committee recommended that the FDA routinely communicate with IRBs about required postmarketing studies — for example, by issuing a letter to accompany IRB applications that conveys information that is material to the IRB’s determination of the ethics of the research, as well as providing additional communications over the life of the study as warranted by new information about the drug or by changes in professional practice. The committee also believed that the FDA was ethically obligated to actually use the findings from required studies to make timely regulatory decisions.

The IOM committee emphasized that the adequacy of the informed-consent process is only one element in the ethics of FDA-required postmarketing research. Other central, and indeed prior, features include ensuring that the selection of participants is equitable and that the level of risk to which they are exposed is acceptable. The committee also recognized, however, that there are challenges to achieving meaningful informed consent in postmarketing trials of drugs for which there is a signal indicating the possibility of drug-related harm. In such cases, there is a suspicion that the benefits of the drug may not justify its risks and often that it may have a worse benefit–risk profile than alternative drugs available to treat the same condition. The committee concluded that for postmarketing trials of such drugs, there are “heightened obligations to ensure that potential research participants understand the risks posed by study enrollment.”4 This was of particular importance for rosiglitazone, because the cardiovascular problem it appeared to cause was the same outcome that good diabetic control was supposed to improve — in other words, if this elevation in risk were real, there could be little offsetting benefit.

The committee recommended several measures to strengthen the consent process in order to maximize patients’ understanding of the context in which the trial is being conducted, including what is already known about the risks associated with the drug. The report discussed both specific disclosures in the informed-consent form and special efforts that could be made to ensure adequate comprehension of complex information regarding risks (Table 2TABLE 2Mechanisms for Strengthening the Informed-Consent Process for Postmarketing Drug-Safety Studies.). To assist IRBs, the committee recommended that the FDA issue guidance interpreting current informed-consent regulatory requirements in the context of required postmarketing studies.

STRENGTHENING POSTMARKETING RESEARCH AND ITS GOVERNANCE

Because a true picture of the benefit–risk profile of a drug only emerges over time, two different IOM committees have stressed the need for the FDA to fully embrace a “life-cycle approach” to drug regulation, in which its obligations to protect public health are taken as seriously once a drug is on the market as they are before approval is granted.4,16 Postmarketing regulatory oversight is assuming heightened importance as the FDA accrues additional authority to fast-track drugs for approval on the basis of more limited evidence than was previously required in order to address unmet medical needs and accelerate innovation.17-19 This changing landscape raises several challenges for ensuring the ethical conduct of research with approved drugs and balancing societal interests in drug innovation and drug safety. We highlight two of these challenges here.

First, not all postmarketing research is ethically equivalent. The TIDE trial represented an iconic kind of postmarketing study: an FDA-required randomized trial to study a drug whose benefit–risk profile was under a cloud of suspicion and at a time when alternative treatments were available, albeit not all well studied. The risks to patients of participating in the trial probably outweighed the prospect of direct benefit. By contrast, when the FDA requires an observational study that uses previously collected data, the clinical experience of the participants is unaffected, the risks incurred are not at the behest of the FDA, and ethical concerns are largely confined to confidentiality and the right to control one’s medical information.

Both of these scenarios can be distinguished from the context in which a phase 4 trial is required as a condition of an accelerated drug approval and is initiated soon thereafter. Here, the trial requirement is not imposed because of a newly emerging concern about a drug already in clinical use but because additional evidence is needed to confirm the initial judgment that the benefits of a new drug are likely to outweigh its risks. Often, this initial judgment is based on the use of a surrogate end point for drug benefit, not on the clinical outcomes that matter most. Especially when the new drug targets an unmet medical need, it may be in the patients’ best interest to take it, pending further timely research. The ensuing trial is undertaken to confirm the improvement in clinical outcomes predicted by the surrogate — a different epistemic and ethical situation than that in which substantial evidence suggests that the surrogate is misleading or that other harms might offset a known clinical benefit.

The volume of phase 4 and other research with FDA-approved drugs is increasing, not only because of the expanded authority of the FDA to require such research but also because of the growing volume of comparative-effectiveness research. In some cases, there may be no or little ethical difference between FDA-required postmarketing research and comparative-effectiveness research initiated by academic investigators. By contrast, a comparative-effectiveness study of two widely used drugs that is not occasioned by heightened concern about the risks of one drug relative to the other is markedly different, ethically, from a study required by the FDA to pursue a safety signal that is already of such concern that practice patterns are shifting, even if both studies use randomized designs.

These differences highlight the need for IRBs to be sensitive to the place where a study falls within the life cycle of a drug and to the reason for the research. Depending on who is initiating the research, for what reasons, and when, the same study design may have very different ramifications for the benefit–risk balance of the study and what patients need to know in order to provide meaningful informed consent. Trials that may be regarded as unethical late in the life cycle because of accumulated evidence can be much easier to initiate earlier if the need for additional research is anticipated and planned at the time of initial approval. In the case of rosiglitazone, this need could have been anticipated from preapproval data showing an adverse effect on serum lipids as well as the use of a surrogate end point (glycemic control) for a first-in-class drug.5,20

Second, the experience with rosiglitazone underscored the fragility of our current system of discovering risks associated with drugs. This system relies heavily on drug sponsors and FDA scientists to conduct safety analyses on the basis of data from clinical trials, some or all of which are not publicly available, and to release findings to the public. It has been shown repeatedly that the published record can misrepresent evidence known to the FDA.21,22 In the case of rosiglitazone, scientists from GlaxoSmithKline and the FDA had information from 42 clinical trials, of which only 7 were published and the others were inaccessible. Triggered by concerns expressed by the World Health Organization in 2006, GlaxoSmithKline conducted and shared with the FDA a meta-analysis of the safety of rosiglitazone that used these data, confirming a possibly elevated risk of ischemic events, but neither these results nor the primary trial results were shared with the public until an unrelated court settlement forced GlaxoSmithKline to release its complete clinical-trial data.23 This access led to the published meta-analysis by independent researchers that made these data and concerns public in 2007.5

It is often the work of independent scientists that has highlighted critical safety problems with approved drugs.5,24-29 Yet currently, data from premarketing studies that are submitted as part of a new drug application or a supplemental new drug application are largely shielded from release to external scientists and the public owing to concerns about a competitive disadvantage to drug sponsors.30,31 The IOM committee stopped short of calling on the FDA to increase public access to such data but recommended that the agency initiate a process to determine ways to “appropriately balance public health, privacy, and proprietary interests to facilitate disclosure” of relevant data.4 Greater transparency would better equip independent scientists to investigate early safety signals.31 Consideration should be given to making drug-safety data from clinical trials available to the public on request once the FDA has reached a decision regarding a new drug application or a supplemental new drug application or once the manufacturer has abandoned the application, unless the manufacturer can articulate a persuasive reason why it would result in competitive harm and the FDA determines that this harm outweighs the public health benefits of releasing the information.

CONCLUSIONS

The experience with rosiglitazone and the TIDE trial offers a lesson in how our current approach to the oversight of drug-safety and postmarketing research can fail both the public and the research participants. Although terminating the TIDE trial was justifiable, it left regulators with highly suggestive but nondefinitive data on the relative safety of rosiglitazone and the closest clinical alternative, pioglitazone.32

Reactive policymaking is tempting but problematic. The history of regulation of human subjects research suggests that rules that are “born in scandal and reared in protectionism”33 often fall short of providing meaningful protections to research participants and that, once adopted, regulations can ossify and become difficult to dislodge. Nevertheless, the IOM committee’s report makes a number of actionable recommendations that the FDA can implement under its existing authority.34 In addition, appointment of an independent ethics advisory board would strengthen the decision making of the FDA as it confronts emerging ethical challenges — both those arising from required postmarketing trials and those stemming from powerful new drug surveillance systems, such as the FDA’s Sentinel Initiative. As the pace of the translation of discoveries from bench to bedside continues to intensify, so too does the imperative for thoughtful ethical governance throughout the life cycle of a drug.

The views expressed in this article are those of the authors and, except where noted, do not represent the official position of the Institute of Medicine or of the committee that produced the report discussed in this article.

Drs. Faden and Goodman chaired, and Dr. Mello was a member of, the Institute of Medicine committee that produced the report discussed in this article.

Disclosure forms provided by the authors are available with the full text of this article at NEJM.org.

This article was published on August 22, 2012, at NEJM.org.

We thank the other IOM committee members for contributing to some of the ideas discussed.

SOURCE INFORMATION

From the Department of Health Policy and Management, Harvard School of Public Health, Boston (M.M.M.); the Departments of Medicine and Health Research and Policy, Stanford University School of Medicine, Stanford, CA (S.N.G.); and the Berman Institute of Bioethics, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore (R.R.F.).

REFERENCES

    1. 1Food and Drug Amendments Act of 2007, Pub. L. No. 110-85, 121 Stat. 823. (2007).

    1. 2London AJ, Kimmelman J, Carlisle B. Research ethics: rethinking research ethics: the case of postmarketing trials. Science 2012;336:544-545
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 3ClinicalTrials.gov. Thiazolidinedione Intervention with Vitamin D Evaluation (TIDE). 2011 (http://clinicaltrials.gov/ct2/show/NCT00879970?term=NCT00879970&rank=1).

    1. 4Committee on Ethical and Scientific Issues in Studying the Safety of Approved Drugs, Institute of Medicine. Ethical and scientific issues in studying the safety of approved drugs. Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 2012 (http://www.iom.edu/Reports/2012/Ethical-and-Scientific-Issues-in-Studying-the-Safety-of-Approved-Drugs.aspx).

    1. 5Nissen SE, Wolski K. Effect of rosiglitazone on the risk of myocardial infarction and death from cardiovascular causes. N Engl J Med 2007;356:2457-2471[Erratum, N Engl J Med 2007;357:100.]
      Full Text | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 6Hamburg M. Letter to the honorable Charles E. Grassley. March 30, 2010 (http://online.wsj.com/public/resources/documents/Grassley.pdf).

    1. 7Lincoff AM, Wolski K, Nicholls SJ, Nissen SE. Pioglitazone and risk of cardiovascular events in patients with type 2 diabetes mellitus: a meta-analysis of randomized trials.JAMA 2007;298:1180-1188
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 8Dormandy JA, Charbonnel B, Eckland DJ, et al. Secondary prevention of macrovascular events in patients with type 2 diabetes in the PROactive Study (PROspective pioglitAzone Clinical Trial In macroVascular Events): a randomised controlled trial. Lancet2005;366:1279-1289
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 9Graham D, Gelperin K. Memorandum to Mary Parks, re: benefit-risk assessment of rosiglitazone vs. pioglitazone. October 7, 2008 (http://www.finance.senate.gov/newsroom/chairman/release/?id=bc56b552-efc5-4706-968d-f7032d5cd2e4).

    1. 10Mahoney K. Advisory committee clinical briefing document: preliminary endocrine medical officer review of the RECORD (Rosiglitazone Evaluated for Cardiac Outcomes and Regulation of Glycemia in Diabetes) Trial, and update on cardiovascular safety information from large clinical trials of rosiglitazone. 2010 (http://www.fda.gov/downloads/AdvisoryCommittees/CommitteesMeetingMaterials/Drugs/EndocrinologicandMetabolicDrugsAdvisoryCommittee/UCM218493.pdf).

    1. 11Baucus M, Grassley C. Letter to the honorable Margaret A. Hamburg, MD. February 18, 2010 (http://www.finance.senate.gov/newsroom/chairman/release/?id=bc56b552-efc5-4706-968d-f7032d5cd2e4).

    1. 12Woodcock J. Decision on continued marketing of rosiglitazone (Avandia, Avandamet, Avandaryl). 2010 (memorandum) (http://www.fda.gov/downloads/Drugs/DrugSafety/PostmarketDrugSafetyInformationforPatientsandProviders/UCM226959.pdf).

    1. 13Woodcock J, Sharfstein JM, Hamburg M. Regulatory action on rosiglitazone by the U.S. Food and Drug Administration. N Engl J Med 2010;363:1489-1491
      Full Text | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 14Food and Drug Administration, Center for Drug Evaluation and Research. Joint meeting of the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee and Drug Safety and Risk Management Advisory Committee. July 14, 2010 (transcript) (http://www.fda.gov/downloads/AdvisoryCommittees/CommitteesMeetingMaterials/Drugs/EndocrinologicandMetabolicDrugsAdvisoryCommittee/UCM222629.pdf).

    1. 15Committee on Ethical and Scientific Issues in Studying the Safety of Approved Drugs, Institute of Medicine. Ethical issues in studying the safety of approved drugs: a letter report. Washington, DC: National Academies Press, July 2010 (http://www.nap.edu/catalog.php?record_id=12948).

    1. 16Committee on the Assessment of the U.S. Drug Safety System, Institute of Medicine. The future of drug safety: promoting and protecting the health of the public. Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 2007 (http://www.iom.edu/Reports/2006/The-Future-of-Drug-Safety-Promoting-and-Protecting-the-Health-of-the-Public.aspx).

    1. 17U.S. Senate. Health, Education, Labor and Pension Committee. Food and Drug Administration Safety and Innovation Act (discussion draft), 112th Cong., 2d Sess. 2012 (http://www.help.senate.gov/imo/media/audio/KER12172.pdf).

    1. 18Chen JY, Carter M. Bioethics and post-approval research in translational science. Am J Bioeth 2010;10:35-37
      Web of Science

    1. 19Psaty BM, Meslin EM, Breckenridge A. A lifecycle approach to the evaluation of FDA approval methods and regulatory actions: opportunities provided by a new IOM report. JAMA 2012 May 4 (Epub ahead of print).

    1. 20Misbin RI. Lessons from the Avandia controversy: a new paradigm for the development of drugs to treat type 2 diabetes. Diabetes Care 2007;30:3141-3144
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 21Doshi P, Jefferson T, Del Mar C. The imperative to share clinical study reports: recommendations from the Tamiflu experience. PLoS Med 2012;9:e1001201-e1001201
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 22Rising K, Bacchetti P, Bero L. Reporting bias in drug trials submitted to the Food and Drug Administration: review of publication and presentation. PLoS Med 2008;5:e217-e217[Erratum, PloS Med 2009;6(1):e17.]
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 23Nissen SE. The rise and fall of rosiglitazone. Eur Heart J 2010;31:773-776
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 24Sackner-Bernstein JD, Kowalski M, Fox M, Aaronson K. Short-term risk of death after treatment with nesiritide for decompensated heart failure: a pooled analysis of randomized controlled trials. JAMA 2005;293:1900-1905
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 25Sackner-Bernstein JD, Skopicki HA, Aaronson KD. Risk of worsening renal function with nesiritide in patients with acutely decompensated heart failure. Circulation 2005;111:1487-1491[Erratum, Circulation 2005;111:2274.]
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 26Nissen SE, Wolski K, Topol EJ. Effect of muraglitazar on death and major adverse cardiovascular events in patients with type 2 diabetes mellitus. JAMA 2005;294:2581-2586
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 27Solomon DH. Selective cyclooxygenase 2 inhibitors and cardiovascular events. Arthritis Rheum 2005;52:1968-1978
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 28Curfman GD, Morrissey S, Drazen JM. Expression of concern: Bombardier et al., “Comparison of upper gastrointestinal toxicity of rofecoxib and naproxen in patients with rheumatoid arthritis,” N Engl J Med 2000;343:1520-8. N Engl J Med 2005;353:2813-2814
      Full Text | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 29Nissen SE, Wolski K. Rosiglitazone revisited: an updated meta-analysis of risk for myocardial infarction and cardiovascular mortality. Arch Intern Med 2010;170:1191-1201
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 30Kesselheim AS, Mello MM. Confidentiality laws and secrecy in medical research: improving public access to data on drug safety. Health Aff (Millwood) 2007;26:483-491
      CrossRef | Web of Science | Medline

    1. 31Krumholz H. The FDA is faster: now let’s make it safer. Outcomes. Forbes.com. May 16, 2012 (http://blogs.forbes.com/harlankrumholz).

    1. 32Punthakee Z, Bosch J, Dagenais G, et al. Design, history and results of the Thiazolidinedione Intervention with vitamin D Evaluation (TIDE) randomised controlled trial.Diabetologia 2012;55:36-45
      CrossRef | Web of Science

    1. 33Levine C. Has AIDS changed the ethics of human subjects research? Law Med Health Care 1988;16:167-173
      Medline

      34

      Food and Drug Administration. Guidance for industry: postmarketing studies and clinical trials — implementation of section 505(o)(3) of the federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act. April 2011 (http://www.fda.gov/downloads/Drugs/GuidanceComplianceRegulatoryInformation/Guidances/UCM172001.pdf).

      http://www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMhle1207160?query=TOC

Read Full Post »